1 Running Head : PROSPECT RELATIVITY Prospect Relativity : How Choice Options Influence Decision Under Risk

نویسندگان

  • Neil Stewart
  • Nick Chater
  • Henry P. Stott
  • Stian Reimers
چکیده

In many theories of decision under risk (e.g., expected utility theory, rank-dependent utility theory, and prospect theory), the utility of a prospect is independent of other options in the choice set. The experiments presented here show a large effect of the available options, suggesting instead that prospects are valued relative to one another. The judged certainty equivalent for a prospect is strongly influenced by the options available. Similarly, the selection of a preferred prospect is strongly influenced by the prospects available. Alternative theories of decision under risk (e.g., the stochastic difference model, multialternative decision field theory, and range frequency theory), where prospects are valued relative to one another, can provide an account of these context effects. Prospect Relativity 3 Prospect Relativity: How Choice Options Influence Decision Under Risk Decisions almost always involve trading off risk and reward. In crossing the road, one balances the risk of accident against the reward of saving time; in choosing a shot in tennis, one balances the risk of an unforced error against the reward of winning. Choosing a career, a life partner, or whether to have children involves trading off different balances between the risks and returns of the prospects available. Understanding how people decide between different levels of risk and return is, therefore, a central question for psychology. Understanding how people trade off risk and return is also a central issue for economics. The foundations of economic theory are rooted in models of individual decision making. For example, to explain the behavior of markets one needs a model of the decisionmaking behavior of buyers and sellers in those markets. Most interesting economic decisions involve risk. Thus, an economic understanding of markets for insurance, of risky assets such as stocks and shares, of the lending and borrowing of money itself, and indeed of the economy at large requires understanding how people trade risk and reward. In both psychology and economics, the starting point for investigating how people make decisions involving risk has not been empirical data on human behavior. Instead, the starting point has been a normative theory of decision making, expected utility (hereafter, EU) theory (axiomatized by von Neumann & Morgenstern, 1947), which specifies how people ought to make decisions and plays a key role in theories of rational choice (for a review, see Shafir & LeBoeuf, 2002). The assumption has then been that, to an approximation, people do make decisions as they ought to, that is, that EU theory can be viewed as a descriptive, as well as a normative, theory of human behavior (Arrow, 1971; Friedman & Savage, 1948). At the core of EU theory are the assumptions that people make choices that maximize their utility and that they value a risky option by the EU (in a probabilistic sense of expectation) that it will provide. In general, the prospect (x1, p1; x2, p2; ... ; xn, pn), where outcome xi occurs with probability pi, and p1 + p2 + ... + pn = 1, has EU Prospect Relativity 4 U x1 , p1 ; x2 , p2 ; ... ; xn , pn = p1 u x1 p2 u x2 ... pn u xn (1) (The function U gives the utility of a risky prospect. The function u is reserved for the utility of certain outcomes only.) In psychology and experimental economics, there has been considerable interest in probing the limits of this approximation, that is, in finding divergence or agreement between EU theory and actual behavior (see, e.g., Kagel & Roth, 1995; Kahneman, Slovic, & Tversky, 1982; Kahneman & Tversky, 2000). It is now well established that people systematically violate the axioms of EU theory (see Camerer, 1995; Luce, 2000; Schoemaker, 1982, for reviews). In economics more broadly, there has been interest in how robustly economic theory copes with anomalies between EU theory and observed behavior (for a range of views, see, e.g., Akerlof & Yellen, 1985; Cyert & de Groot, 1974; de Canio, 1979; Friedman, 1953; Nelson & Winter, 1982; Simon, 1959, 1992). The present article demonstrates a new and large anomaly for EU theory in decision making under risk. Specifically, we report results that seem to indicate that people do not possess a well-defined notion of the utility of a risky prospect and hence, a fortiori, do not view such utilities in terms of EU. Instead, people's perceived utility for a risky prospect appears highly context sensitive. We call this phenomenon prospect relativity. Motivation From Psychophysics In judging risky prospects, people must assess the magnitudes of risk and return that the prospects comprise. The motivation for the experiments presented here was the idea that some of the factors that determine how people assess these magnitudes might be analogous to factors underlying assessment of psychophysical magnitudes, such as loudness or weight. Specifically, people appear poor at providing stable absolute judgments of such magnitudes and are heavily influenced by the options available to them. For example, Garner (1954) asked participants to judge whether tones were more or less than half as loud as a 90-dB reference loudness. Participants' judgments were entirely determined by the range of tones played to Prospect Relativity 5 them. Participants played tones in the range 55-65 dB had a half-loudness point, where their judgments were more than half as loud 50% of the time and less than half as loud 50% of the time, of about 60 dB. Another group, which received tones in the range 65-75 dB, had a halfloudness point of about 70 dB. A final group, who heard tones in the range 75-85 dB, had a half-loudness point of about 80 dB. Laming (1997) provided an extensive discussion of other similar findings. Context effects, like those found by Garner, are consistent with participants making perceptual judgments on the basis of relative magnitude information, rather than absolute magnitude information (Laming, 1984, 1997; Stewart, Brown, & Chater, 2002a, 2002b). If the attributes of risky prospects behave like those of perceptual stimuli, then similar context effects should be expected in risky decision making. This hypothesis motivated the experiments in this article, experiments that were loosely based on Garner's procedure. Existing Experimental Investigations A few experiments have already investigated the effect of the set of available options in decision under risk. Mellers, Ordóñez, and Birnbaum (1992) measured participants' attractiveness ratings and buying prices (i.e., the price that a participant would pay to obtain a single chance to play the prospect and have a chance of receiving the outcome) for a set of simple binary prospects of the form "p chance of x." These experimental prospects were presented with one of two sets of filler prospects. For one set of filler prospects, the distribution of expected values was positively skewed, and for the other set, the distribution of expected values was negatively skewed. Attractiveness ratings of the experimental prospects were significantly influenced by the filler prospects, with higher ratings for prospects in the positive skew condition than for the same prospects in the negative skew condition. However, context had only a very small effect on buying price. With more complicated prospects of the form "p chance of x otherwise y," the effect of skew on buying price was slightly larger. The large effect that the set of options available had on attractiveness ratings and the much smaller effect on buying price are consistent with a similar demonstration by Janiszewski and Prospect Relativity 6 Lichtenstein (1999). They gave participants a set of prices for different brands of the same product to study. The prices varied in range. The range had an effect on judgments of the attractiveness of a new price but not on the amount participants reported that they would expect to pay for a new product. The set of options available as potential certainty equivalents (hereafter, CEs) has been shown to affect the choice of CE for risky prospects. In making a CE judgment, participants suggest or select from a set of options the amount of money for certain that is worth the same to them as a single chance to play the prospect. We considered CE judgments extensively in our experiments. Birnbaum (1992) demonstrated that skewing the distribution of options offered as CEs for simple prospects, while holding the maximum and minimum constant, influenced the selection of a CE. When the options were positively skewed (i.e., when most values were small) prospects were undervalued compared to when the options were negatively skewed (i.e., when most values were large). MacCrimmon, Stanbury, and Wehrung (1980) presented some evidence that the set in which a prospect is embedded can affect judgments about the prospect. They presented participants with two sets of five prospects to be ranked in order of attractiveness. The expected value of each prospect was constant across all prospects and both sets. There were two prospects in common between the two sets. If context provided by the other prospects in a set did not affect the attractiveness of a prospect, each participant should have consistently ranked one prospect as more attractive than the other in both sets. MacCrimmon et al. found that 9 of a total of 40 participants had a different ordering of the two prospects in the two sets. They argued that this was not merely inconsistency, because these participants made consistent rankings within a set, but instead reflected the influence of the other prospects in the choice set. Following this logic, however, it would take only one participant who had a different ordering of the two prospects but who otherwise behaved consistently to conclude that there was an effect of choice set. A random fluctuation in risk aversion between sets Prospect Relativity 7 might produce this result. With such a small number of data points and no concrete null hypothesis allowing a significance test to be made any conclusion based on this results must be very tentative. In summary, there is an effect of previously considered prospects on the attractiveness rating assigned to a current prospect and also a small effect on buying price. Moreover, the context provided by a set of values from which a CE is to be chosen affects CE judgments. Finally, in choosing between prospects, there is a suggestion that other prospects in the choice set may reverse preferences between identical pairs of prospects. In the experiments reported below we found large and systematic effects of choice set (both potential CEs and accompanying prospects) on the valuation of individual prospects. These effects are not compatible with EU theory or some of its most influential variants, according to which the value of a prospect is independent of other available options. These results are, though, compatible with a variety of models that discard this independence assumption. We consider such models in the General Discussion. Summary of Experiments As indicated above, in this study we adapt methodologies from psychophysics to investigate the possibility that context effects influence decision under risk. The aim of Experiments 1A-1D was to determine whether options offered as potential CEs influenced estimates of a prospect's CE. We consistently found substantial effects. In Experiment 2, to investigate these effects, we introduce a new procedure in which, under certain assumptions, it was optimal for participants to provide truthful CEs. In Experiment 3, we examined whether these effects were similar to those observed in magnitude estimation tasks. In the remaining two experiments, Experiments 4 and 5, we investigated whether the effect of available options arose in choices between prospects as well as in CE judgments about prospects. Experiment 1A Following a similar logic to Garner's (1954) loudness judgment experiment described Prospect Relativity 8 above, we gave participants a set of four options as possible CEs for a series of prospects. Participants were asked to decide on a CE for the prospect and then select the option closest to their estimate. For each prospect, options were either all lower in value than the mean free choice CE (given by another group of participants) or all higher.1 If participants were not influenced by the set of options, then their choice of option should have been that nearest to their free-choice CE. A key prediction of this hypothesis is that either the highest option of the low options (L4), the lowest option of the high options (H1), or both should be chosen more than half of the time. Consider the distribution of free-choice CEs illustrated in Figure 1A. If H1 is to be selected less than half of the time, then the area to the left of the H1-H2 bound must be less than one half. This area corresponds to the proportion of times that the free choice CE is nearest to H1. Thus, the area to the right (labeled Area A) must be greater than one half. This means that the proportion of times that L4 will be selected from the low options must be greater than one half, as this proportion corresponds to the sum of area to the right of the H1H2 bound (Area A which was greater that half) and the area between the L3-L4 and H1-H2 bounds (Area B which depends on the exact probability density function, but must be greater than or equal to zero). This argument is true for any probability density function. Similarly, if L4 is selected less than half of the time, H1 must be selected more than half of the time (Figure 1B). The selection of L4 less than half of the time and H1 less than half of the time is not consistent with any distribution of free-choice CEs that is not affected by context. If participants' responses were solely determined by the set of options presented to them, however, then the distribution of responses across options should have been the same for both the lowand the high-value options. Method Participants. Free-choice CEs were given by 14 psychology undergraduates from the University of Warwick. Another 16 psychology undergraduates chose CEs from sets of options. All participated for course credit. Ages ranged from 18 to 20 years. All but three Prospect Relativity 9 participants were female. Design. A set of 20 prospects, each of the form "p chance of x," was created by crossing the amounts £200, £400, £600, £800, and £1000 with the probabilities .2, .4, .6, and .8. In a pretest, 14 participants were asked to provide a CE for each prospect. The means and standard deviations of the free choice CEs were calculated for each prospect (see Appendix A). For each prospect, two sets of options were created as follows. In the low-options condition, the options were 1/6, 2/6, 3/6, and 4/6 of a standard deviation below the mean. In the high options condition, options were 1/6, 2/6, 3/6, and 4/6 of a standard deviation above the mean. Thus, the range of each set was half a standard deviation. Options were rounded to have familiar, easy-to-deal-with values. Sixteen new participants were presented with the prospects and options and asked to select the option closest to their CE from a set of four. Eight participants received the low options for every prospect. The other eight received the high options for every prospect. Note that this method, in which a range of potential CEs is presented, is not uncommon in other experimental work in this area (see, e.g., Tversky & Kahneman, 1992). Procedure. Participants were asked to imagine choosing between "£30 for certain" or a "50% chance of £100" to illustrate that prospects could have a value. They were told they would be asked to value a series of prospects. It was explained that the purpose of the experiment was to investigate how much they thought the prospects were worth and that there were no correct answers. Participants were asked to choose the option nearest the value they thought the prospect was worth to them. Each prospect was presented on a separate page of a 20-page booklet. The ordering of the prospects was random and different for each participant. Probabilities were always presented as percentages. Options were always presented in numerical order, as in the following example of a low-option set: Prospect Relativity 10 How much is the gamble "60% chance of £400" worth? Is it: £60 £80 £100 £120 When collecting pretest free-choice CEs, the options were omitted, and a blank line on which participants could write their CE was added. Results Participants took approximately 5 minutes to complete the task. Under free-choice conditions, the average CE (see Appendix A) increased with both probability of winning and the amount that could be won, demonstrating that participants were sensitive to manipulations of both. The chosen CE was an approximately linear function of the independent effects of prospect amount and prospect probability. The proportion of times each option was chosen is plotted in Figure 2. The distribution of options is approximately the same for the two conditions. L4 was chosen significantly less than half the time, t(7) = 4.21, p = .0040 ( 2 = .72). The same was true of H1, t(7) = 5.26, p = .0012 ( 2 = .80). Thus the hypothesis that participants' CEs would be unaffected by context can be rejected. (An alpha level of .05 was used for all statistical tests in this article, but for informational value, we also report the exact p value of each test.2) Discussion CE judgments were strongly influenced by the CE options offered. These data therefore appear to illustrate prospect relativity: People do not seem to form a stable absolute judgment of the value of a prospect but instead choose an option relative to the options available. The preference for central options in each set may be an example of extremeness aversion (also called the compromise effect; see Simonson & Tversky, 1992). Indeed, these data may reflect a more general tendency to prefer central options that is seen when choosing among identical options (e.g., products on a supermarket shelf; Christenfeld, 1995). Prospect Relativity 11 Experiment 1B A natural explanation of the effect of the set of options available in Experiment 1A is that, on a given trial, the options available affected a participant's judgment. However, an alternative and, for our purposes, less interesting explanation is that when participants were repeatedly presented with trials containing too-high or too-low options, they learned to readjust their judgments to fit their responses within the alternatives given. One way of ruling out this alternative explanation was to use a within-participants design. In this design each participant was presented with some trials on which all the options were lower than the freechoice CE and others on which all the options were higher. If the effect seen previously had been caused by participants learning to adjust their judgments up or down to fit into the response scale, the effect should now have disappeared. However, if the effect was caused by the options available on that trial only, then the pattern of results demonstrated in Experiment 1A should have been be replicated. Method Participants. Free-choice CEs were given by 35 volunteers. Twenty-eight different volunteers chose CEs from sets of options. All participants were undergraduates or postgraduates from the University of Warwick, and none had participated in Experiment 1A. Ages ranged from 18 to 30 years, with a mean of 22 years. Two thirds of participants were female. Participants were paid £5 for taking part in this and other related experiments. Design and procedure. The design was the same as in Experiment 1 except that for each participant, 10 trials were randomly selected to have options all higher than the pretest mean for that prospect, the other 10 having options all below the mean. Trials were randomly intermixed. Free-choice CEs and corresponding options are given in Appendix B. The procedure was the same as in Experiment 1A. Results Participants took approximately 5 minutes to complete the task. One participant's data Prospect Relativity 12 were excluded from the analysis because he had been given a misleading answer to a query about the task that would have led to an inappropriate response strategy. As before, under free choice, the CE increased approximately linearly with both the amount that could be won and the probability of winning. Figure 3 shows the proportion of choices of each option. In both conditions, the proportion of responses increases with proximity to the mean free-choice CE. Planned t tests showed that the proportions of L4 and H1 responses were significantly below .5, t(26) = 2.65, p = .0135 ( 2 = .21), and t(26) = 3.81, p = .0008 ( 2 = .36), respectively. A further issue is whether the context effects found in the main analysis applied to all participants or whether some people showed a larger context effect than others. For each participant, two scores were constructed, one for each condition. Participants were awarded one point for each time they chose the lowest option, two for the next lowest, three for the second highest, and four for the highest (i.e., scores were the rank of the options selected in each condition). Those showing no effect of the option set should have chosen the L4 and H1. However, those who based their judgment entirely on the option set would choose midrange options. Thus, a negative correlation between low-choice CEs and high-choice CEs would be evidence that people varied in the extent to which context influenced their CE decisions. Far from being negatively correlated, there was a significant positive correlation (r2 = .45, p = . 0001). One interpretation of this positive correlation is that participants had a tendency to choose an option with the same rank across the lowand high-choice CE conditions. (Note that this analysis could not be run for Experiment 1A because the set of options was manipulated between participants.) Perhaps surprisingly, we found no evidence that the options offered on the previous trial influenced the option selected on the current trial. One might imagine that, say, offering low options on the previous trial might cause participants who were trying to be consistent to have selected an option lower than they otherwise would on the current trial. However, the Prospect Relativity 13 rank (as described above) of the option selected within the set did not depend on the previous option set offered (mean rank = 2.63, SE = 0.11, for prior low options vs. mean rank = 2.62, SE = 0.13, for prior high options), t(26) = 0.23, p = .8407. This test is sufficiently sensitive to be able to detect a difference of 0.21 between the mean ranks with a power of 80%.3 Discussion As in Experiment 1A, participants' CE judgments in Experiment 1B were influenced, at least in part, by the options from which the CE had to be chosen. In Experiment 1B, there was a tendency to prefer higher options from the low CEs set and lower options from the high CEs set. (This contrasts with Experiment 1A, where there was no such tendency.) Overall, the pattern of results shown in Experiment 1B is intermediate between that expected under the hypothesis that the available options are irrelevant and that expected if the available options are the only determinant of responses. The tendency in Experiment 1B can be accounted for in three ways. First, the effect in Experiment 1A may have been partly caused by participants readjusting their responses to fit in with the options available. In Experiment 1B, such an adjustment need not have been made as the option set was manipulated within participants, and thus a smaller context effect was observed. However, this explanation still requires an additional factor, such as prospect relativity, to contribute to the effects seen in Experiments 1A and 1B. A second explanation of the tendency is that the absolute spacing of the options differed between Experiments 1A and 1B. In both experiments, the spacing of CE options was set at 1/6 of a free-choice SD. However, the free-choice SDs were smaller in Experiment 1B, and thus, the absolute values of the options were actually more closely spaced in Experiment 1B.4 For this reason, we replicated Experiments 1A and 1B as conditions of a single experiment, using the spacings from Experiment 1B throughout. The between-participants result was similar to those of Experiment 1A and the within-participants result similar to those of Experiment 1B, so we have not presented them here. An explanation of the different pattern Prospect Relativity 14 of preferences in Experiments 1A and 1B in terms of using different options can thus be ruled out. A third explanation of the difference between Experiments 1A and 1B, and one that we favor, is that participants may have been trying to be consistent with their responses to previously completed questions. Thus, encountering both low and high CE options caused participants to seem less affected by context. Such a consistency effect cannot be due to the immediately preceding trial alone as there was no effect of the immediately preceding trial. Instead, if this kind of explanation is correct, the tendency must be due to some larger window of previous trials. Experiment 1C The effect of available options in Experiments 1A and 1B appears to create difficulties for EU and related theories as descriptive accounts of decision under risk. Yet these difficulties may be less pressing if the effects demonstrated thus far arose only because the options presented as CEs were simply too close together, and that participants were roughly indifferent between them. (Although note that this ought to lead to a u-shaped preference across the options, rather than an n-shape.5) If this were the case then these effects should disappear when the options are more widely spaced and hence are no longer indifferent between them. In Experiment 1C, we investigated the effect of increasing the spacing of the options. Method The method was the same as in Experiment 1B (i.e., low and high options were presented within participants) except that there were three between-participants spacing conditions. In the narrow condition, options were spaced at 1/6 of a free-choice standard deviation as in Experiments 1A and B. In the wide condition, the spacing between adjacent options was doubled to one third of a free-choice standard deviation, and thus the wide condition differed from the narrow condition both in the spacing of the options and in the Prospect Relativity 15 means of the option sets. A gap condition was introduced, with the option spacing of the narrow condition and the option group means of the wide condition. Thus, the gap condition differed from the narrow condition only on the mean of the sets and from the wide condition only on the spacing of the options. Eighteen undergraduate and postgraduate students from the University of Warwick took part in the gap condition, and 19 in each of the narrow and wide conditions. Ages ranged from 18 to 30 years, with a mean of 22 years. Two thirds of participants were female. Results The proportion of times each option was selected is shown in Figure 4. In the narrow condition, option L4 was selected significantly less than half the time, t(18) = 4.02, p = .0008 ( 2 = .47), as was the H1 option, t(18) = 3.42, p = .0031 ( 2 = .39), replicating the results of Experiment 1B. In the wide condition, option L4 was selected less than half the time, t(18) = 2.04, p = .0565 ( 2 = .19), although this difference is only marginally significant. The H1 option was selected significantly less than half of the time, t(18) = 3.52, p = .0024 ( 2 = .41). The key result is that doubling the spacing of the options did not eliminate the context effect. In the gap condition, L4 was not chosen significantly less than half of the time, t(17) = 0.17, p = .8665, but H1 was, t(17) = 2.99, p = .0082 ( 2 = .34). The differences between the conditions were examined with a two-way (Condition x Option Set) univariate analysis of variance (ANOVA), with the mean rank of the option selected as the dependent measure. (It was not possible to run a Condition x Option Set x Option ANOVA, as the selection of options was not independent: The proportion of times each option was selected must sum to 1.) There was no significant main effect of condition, F(2, 53) < 1.00. There was a significant main effect of set, F(1, 53) = 56.16, p < .0001 ( 2 = .51). Participants chose options with higher ranks in the low-options condition compared with the high-options condition. The interaction was also significant, F(2, 53) = 4.00, p = . 0241 ( 2 = .13). The tendency to prefer L4 and H1 was larger in the wide and gap condition Prospect Relativity 16 than the other conditions. To examine the interaction further, we ran a one-way univariate ANOVA with condition as a factor and the difference in ranks between the low and high options as the dependent measure. Ryan REGWQ post hoc tests revealed that the tendency to respond with high-ranking low options and low-ranking high options (i.e., the central tendency) was significantly smaller for the narrow condition, with no difference between the wide and gap conditions. There was a marginally significant positive correlation between the mean rank of the options selected in the lowand high-options trials in the narrow-option spacing condition, r2 = .20, t(17) = 2.07, p = .0543. This replicates the correlation seen in Experiment 1B. This correlation was not seen in the wide, r2 = .01, t(17) = 0.45, p = .6574, and gap conditions, r2 = .05, t(16) = 0.95, p = .3570. A correlation of r2 .35 can be detected with 80% power in this design. Despite the failure to find positive correlations in the wide and gap conditions, there is reason to think the positive correlations seen in the narrow condition of this experiment and in Experiment 1B are reliable: We have replicated the correlation in the replication of Experiments 1A and 1B reported in the discussion of Experiment 1B and also in a further, unpublished study. As in Experiment 1B, we investigated whether there was an effect of the option set offered on the previous trial on the option selected on the current trial. A two-way (Condition x Previous Option Set) ANOVA was run, with the rank of the option selected on the current trial as the dependent measure. There was no significant main effect of condition, F(2, 53) = 1.38, p = .2601. As in Experiment 1B, there was no significant main effect of the previous option set, F(1, 53) < 1.00 (mean rank of option selected on current trial with low options on the previous trial = 2.51, SE = 0.05, vs. a mean rank = 2.50, SE = 0.07, with high options of the previous trial). (A single t test for the difference in mean ranks between the lowand highoption sets can detect a difference of .17 with a power of 80%.) There was no significant interaction, F(2, 53) = 2.12, p = .1301. Prospect Relativity 17 Discussion The effect of the options offered as CEs seen in Experiment 1B was replicated in the narrow condition of Experiment 1C. Doubling the spacing of the options in the wide condition did not eliminate the effect. However, there was a greater tendency to select lower options from the high set and higher options from the low set in the wide and gap conditions when the difference between the means of the option sets was larger. We consider two possible accounts of this result. First, increasing the set mean spacing may have caused participants to rely more on some representation of the absolute utility of each prospect. Perhaps this might be because they realized that the options were quite different from some approximate representation of the utilities of the prospects. However, in this case one might have expected the effect to be larger in the wide rather than the gap condition as the wide condition contained the more disparate options. In fact, the difference, although nonsignificant, was in the opposite direction. A second explanation is that increasing the spacing of the set means should have increased a consistency effect where participants tried to give consistent answers across the lowand high-option sets. Both explanations offer an account of the lack of a correlation between the rank of the options selected across the lowand high-option sets for the wide and gap conditions. Consistency between the lowand high-option sets should have caused participants to select low options from the high set and high options from the low set, as should an increased reliance upon the prospects' absolute utilities. Thus, consistency should have caused a negative correlation that would have acted in opposition to the positive correlation observed in Experiment 1B and the narrow condition here, leaving a net zero correlation. Experiment 1D Experiment 1D aimed to discriminate between the two explanations of the tendency to select L4 options from the low set and H1 options from the high set seen in the wide and gap conditions of Experiment 1C. If the tendency was due to a consistency effect between the low Prospect Relativity 18 and high sets, then repeating the experiment with option set as a between-participants variable should have eliminated the effect. Alternatively, if the wider spacing somehow caused participants to rely more on some representation of absolute utilities, then the greater central tendency should also have been seen in the wide spacing condition even if a given participant saw only low options or only high options. For this reason, in Experiment 1D, option set manipulated between participants. Method Participants. Sixty professionals attending a conference at the University of Warwick were approached on the campus and asked to participate. Participants' ages ranged between 20 and 40 years, with a mean of 27 years. An approximately equal number of male and female participants took part. Design and procedure. Spacing (narrow or wide) and option set (low or high) were manipulated between participants: Fifteen participants took part in each condition. In the wide condition, the low options were set at .10, .20, .30, and .40 of the expected value of each gamble. The high options were set at .60, .70, .80, and .90 of the expected value. In the narrow condition, the interval between options was halved. The low options were set at .30, . 35, .40, and .45 of the expected value. The high options were set at .55, .60, .65, and .70 of the expected value. In other respects, the procedure was the same as in previous experiments.6 Results The proportion of times each option was selected is shown in Figure 5. Overall, there was a preference for the lowest options. This was caused by some participants stating that they did not gamble and then selecting the lowest option on every trial. In the narrow condition, option L4 was selected significantly less than half the time, t(14) = 5.69, p = .0001 ( 2 = .70), as was the H1 option, t(14) = 2.31, p = .0368 ( 2 = .28), replicating the results of Experiment 1A. In the wide condition, option L4 was selected less than half the time, t(14) = 2.17, p = .0477 ( 2 = .25), as was the H1 option, t(14) = 2.33, p = .0354 ( 2 = .28). Doubling Prospect Relativity 19 the spacing of the options did not eliminate the context effect. As in Experiment 1C, a twoway (Spacing x Option Set) ANOVA was run, with the mean rank of the option selected as the dependent measure. There was no main effect of spacing, F(1, 56) < 1. In contrast with Experiment 1C, there was no main effect of option set, F(1, 56) < 1, and no interaction, F(1, 56) < 1. As option set was manipulated between participants the correlation across option sets and the effect of the option set on the previous trial could not be examined. Discussion In Experiment 1C, where option set was manipulated within participants, there was a greater tendency to prefer L4 and H1 when the options were widely spaced. However, such a tendency was not evident here, when option set was manipulated across participants. Thus, not all of the central tendency evident in Experiment 1C can be attributed to participants relying more on some representation of absolute utilities: Instead, at least some of this effect must be due to consistency across option sets. Summary of Experiments 1A-1D To sum up thus far, Experiment 1A demonstrated that the options presented as CEs had a large effect on CE judgments for simple prospects. In Experiment 1B, the set of options was manipulated within participants to investigate whether the results of Experiment 1A might be due to participants adjusting their CE estimates over the course of the experiment to fit in with the options offered. However, the context effect remained. In Experiment 1C, the spacing of the options was increased to investigate the limits of this prospect relativity. However, even when the options were widely spaced, there was an effect of option set. A greater tendency to prefer high options from the set of low options and low options from the set of high options was seen when options were more widely spaced. In Experiment 1D, the greater tendency was not observed when the different option sets were presented across participants. This suggests that the tendency was due, at least in part, to participants attempting to be consistent across conditions in the within-participant designs, rather than participants relying more on some Prospect Relativity 20 representation of absolute utilities. Experiment 2 In Experiments 1A-1D, the set of options offered as CEs affected the CE selected. Experiment 2 was designed to demonstrate the same effect of restricting the range of CE options in a task where it was optimal for participants to report CEs truthfully. Although psychologists typically assume that participants are honest when providing hypothetical CEs, economists are typically concerned with providing a system of incentives that ensures it is optimal for participants to provide truthful CEs. Hence, the results above may be criticized from an economic perspective. There is evidence that psychologists are correct in their assumption that participants are typically honest in their judgments. For example, Lichtenstein and Slovic (1971) demonstrated preference reversals in choices between two prospects and in CE estimates for those prospects in situations where decisions were hypothetical and in situations where there was an incentive system (see also Tversky, Slovic, & Kahneman, 1990). Preference reversals have also been demonstrated with ordinary gamblers playing for high stakes in Las Vegas (Lichtenstein & Slovic, 1973; see also Grether & Plott, 1979). For further discussion of these and other similar findings, see Hertwig and Ortmann (2001) and Luce (2000, pp. 15-16). However, because of the potential importance of the findings from Experiments 1A-1D for models of economics, we include this experiment where the incentive system had been designed to motivate participants to provide truthful CEs. The design follows a solution to the cake-cutting problem, where a cake must be divided fairly between two children. One solution is to allow one child to cut the cake into two pieces and the other child to select the piece. The first child should cut the cake exactly in half, otherwise the other child will take the larger piece of cake, leaving the first child with the smaller piece. In this experiment, participants divided a sum of money into an amount for certain and Prospect Relativity 21 an amount that could be be won with a known, fixed probability. For example, they might split £1,000 into a sure amount of £300 and the prospect "60% chance of £700." Participants knew that the other person (who was not the experimenter) would select either the prospect or the sure amount, taking the better of the two, leaving the participant with the other. Thus, it was optimal for participants to split the given amount so that they had no preference between the resulting fixed amount and the resulting prospect. Note that this procedure works only if each participant assumes that the chooser has the same level of risk preference as himself or herself. To this end, participants were told to assume that the chooser did have the same risk preference as they did. This procedure is more simple than other methods used to elicit truthful CEs, for example, the first price auction, or the Becker, DeGroot, and Marschak (BDM; 1964) procedure. In the BDM procedure, participants are given the chance to play a prospect and are asked to state the minimum price at which they would sell the prospect. A buying price is then randomly generated by the experimenter, and if it exceeds the selling price, then the prospect is bought from the participant. If not, then the participant plays the prospect. It is the case that it is optimal for participants to state a selling price that is the CE of the prospect, though it is unlikely that many participants realize this. Method Participants. Participants were psychology undergraduates from the University of Warwick who had not participated in Experiments 1A-1D. Ages ranged from 18 to 25 years, with a mean age of 20 years. The majority of participants were female. Seventeen participants took part in the free-choice condition of the experiment. Nineteen further participants took part in the restricted-choice conditions. Participants were paid £5, plus performance-related winnings of up to £4. Design. In each trial of the free-choice condition, participants divided a given amount of money x into two smaller amounts y and z to make one fixed amount (y) and the prospect Prospect Relativity 22 "p chance of z." Probability p was known to participants before splitting amount x. Participants were told that one trial in the experiment would be selected at random at the end of the experiment and that a second person would take either the fixed amount or the prospect for himself, leaving the participant with the other option. Under the assumption that the chooser had the same risk preference as they did, it was explained to participants that the chooser would choose the option with greater utility, leaving the participants with their less preferred option, if they did not split the amount to make options of equal utility. It was therefore optimal for participants to split the amount x into amounts y and z such that y and a "p chance of z" were equivalent for them, that is, that y was the CE for the prospect "p chance of z." The restricted-choice conditions differed by offering participants a choice from a set of four pre-split options rather than giving them a completely free choice. That is, values for y and z were presented, and participants selected one pair that could be played at the end of the experiment. It could be argued that participants might reasonably think that the pairs of y and z values presented might provide them with information about the chooser's risk preferences. For this reason, two people were used in running the experiment. One person was responsible for administering the tests and the other for making the choice at the end of the experiment. The intention was to keep the roles of the experimenter and the person making the choice at the end of the experiment separate in participants' minds to minimize the degree to which participants would think that the options provided information about the chooser's risk preference. It was hypothesized, as in Experiments 1A-1D, that the set of pairs of values for y and z presented would influence participants' choices. To investigate this, we varied one betweenparticipants factor. The set of values for y and z were selected such that either y was always greater than the mean free-choice value of y and z was smaller than the mean free-choice value of z, or vice versa. These corresponded to the lowand high-option sets in Experiments Prospect Relativity 23 1A-1D. The precise option sets were constructed as follows. The mean and standard deviation of the free-choice amount were calculated for each prospect (see Appendix C). The two sets of equally spaced options (for the high-value and low-value conditions) were calculated as described for Experiment 1A. As in Experiment 1A, if participants were not influenced by the set of choices, then the distribution of responses across the options should not have been biased towards the free-choice splitting. There were 32 trials in the experiment, made by crossing four values of p (.2, .4, .6, and .8) with eight values of x (£250, £500, ... , £2,000). Procedure. All conditions of the experiment began with written instructions. It was explained to participants that they were playing a gambling game and that they should try to win as much money as possible. They were told that a single trial would be randomly selected at the end of the experiment and used to determine their bonus. They were told the purpose of the experiment was to investigate how much people thought various prospects were worth. It was emphasized that it was optimal for the participants to split the money so they thought the amount for certain was equal in worth to a chance on the prospect. Participants were told that if they allocated funds so that either the amount for certain was worth more than the prospect or vice versa, then the chooser would take the better option, leaving them with less than if they had allocated the money so the prospect was worth the certain amount. They were told that although they could not be certain what the chooser would do, they should assume that the chooser would behave as they would themselves. Participants were given five practice trials. One of the trials was chosen at random, and it was explained that if the chooser chose the fixed amount, then the prospect would be played, and the participants would get the winnings. They were also told that if instead the chooser took the prospect, they would get the fixed amount. Note that this discussion was hypothetical and that participants were not actually told what the chooser's preference would be. After the practice participants completed a booklet of options. The pairs of options Prospect Relativity 24 were presented in a random order to each participant. An example page from a free-choice condition booklet is shown in Figure 6A. In the restricted-choice conditions, presplit options were presented as in Figure 6B. When the experiment was completed, one trial was chosen at random and played to determine each participant's bonus (using an experiment exchange rate of 0.0024). Results Participants took between half an hour and one hour to complete the booklet. It seems that the introduction of a bonus caused participants to deliberate on their answers for much longer than in Experiments 1A-1D. One participant from the free-choice condition was eliminated from subsequent analysis for showing a completely different pattern of results to other participants, suggesting he had misunderstood the task. The participant had decreased the value of the fixed amount y as the chance of the prospect amount p increased (i.e., he had responded as if prospects with a higher chance of winning were worth less to him). Fourteen out of 512 trials (16 participants x 32 trials) where the initial amount had been incorrectly split, were deleted and treated as missing data. For the free-choice splits, as the total amount x increased, participants' allocation of the fixed amount y increased. As the probability p of winning the prospect increased, participants' estimates of the value of the prospect y also increased. Thus, participants' responses seemed lawful and sensible, indicating that the task made sense to them. The choices made in the restricted-choice conditions are shown in Figure 7. Participants did prefer end options over central options in both conditions, as would be expected if participants were not influenced by the option set. However, if there were no effect of context, L4 and H1 should have been chosen over half of the time. L4 was chosen significantly less than half of the time, t(9) = 3.47, p = .0070 ( 2 = .57), as was H1, t(8) = 4.20, p = .0023 ( 2 = .69). Thus, the proportion of times each option was selected differed significantly from the proportions expected under the assumption that participants were not Prospect Relativity 25 influenced by the options available. Discussion The results of the restricted-choice conditions in Experiment 2 replicate the prospect relativity finding shown in Experiment 1 under a more rigorous procedure. When participants were presented with a range of presplit total amounts, so that the CE options were either always lower or always higher than the free-choice value, the context provided by the presplit options influenced their choice of CE. Experiment 3 The demonstration of apparent prospect relativity in risky decision making suggests that the representation of the utility dimension may be similar to that of perceptual psychological dimensions, where context effects have also been demonstrated. Empirical investigations in absolute identification (Garner, 1953; Holland & Lockhead, 1968; Hu, 1997; Lacouture, 1997; Lockhead, 1984; Long, 1937; Luce, Nosofsky, Green, & Smith, 1982; Purks, Callahan, Braida, & Durlach, 1980; Staddon, King, & Lockhead, 1980; Stewart, 2001; Stewart et al., 2002a; Ward & Lockhead, 1970, 1971), magnitude estimation, matching tasks, and relative intensity judgment (see, e.g., Jesteadt, Luce, & Green, 1977; Lockhead & King, 1983; Stevens, 1975, p. 275) have shown that perceptual judgments of stimuli varying along a single psychological continuum are strongly influenced by the preceding material. If the representation of utility is similar to the representation of these simple perceptual dimensions, then preceding material might be expected to influence current judgments, as it does in the perceptual case. Simonson and Tversky (1992) provided several cases where preceding material does indeed influence current judgments in decision making. For example, when choosing between pairs of computers that vary in price and amount of memory, the trade-off between the two attributes in the previous choice affects the current choice. Indeed, preference reversals can be obtained by varying the preceding products. In Experiment 3, we considered the effect of Prospect Relativity 26 preceding material on judgments concerning a single dimension (utility) rather than the tradeoff between two dimensions. Participants simply provided CEs for simple prospects of the form "p chance of x." We then examined the effect of preceding prospects on the CE assigned to the current prospect. Method Participants. Fourteen undergraduates from the University of Warwick participated for payment of £3. All participants had previously taken part in the free-choice condition of Experiment 2. Design. Participants were asked to state the value of a series of prospects. Participants had previously taken part in a task where estimating the value of prospects truthfully optimized their reward, compared with overestimating or underestimating the value of a prospect. Participants were instructed to continue providing CEs in the same way. Ten sets of 10 simple prospects of the form "p chance of x" were constructed. Figure 8 shows the values of p and x for each prospect. Each set of prospects lying on the same curve (these are hyperbolas) shares a common expected value. (The slight deviation of the crosses from the line is caused by rounding the values of p and x.) Prospects were chosen in this fashion simply because it produces an equal number of prospects with each expected value. The order in which prospects were presented was random and different for each participant. We hypothesized that the preceding prospect should affect the value assigned to the current prospect as follows. If the previous prospect had a low expected value, then we expected that the current prospect would be overvalued. Conversely, if the previous prospect had a high expected value, then we expected that the current prospect would be undervalued. This prediction was motivated by the contrast effects observed in the analogous perceptual task, magnitude estimation. Procedure. Participants were told that they would be asked to value prospects and that they should do this in the same way as in the previous experiment (the free-choice condition of Prospect Relativity 27 Experiment 2). Participants completed a booklet with a separate prospect on each page, together with a space for their valuation. Results Figure 9 plots the mean value of prospects, as a function of the expected value of the previous prospect, for each possible expected value of the current prospect. CEs given to a prospect increased as the expected value of the prospect increased. The response was, on average, 97% of the expected value (SD = 36%) showing slight risk aversion, on average. The expected value of the previous prospect had no effect on the value assigned to the current prospect (i.e., the lines in Figure 9 are flat). To examine possible sequence effects more closely, we completed a linear regression for each participant to see what proportion of the variability in the current response could be explained by the previous prospect's expected value after the effects of the attributes of the current prospect had been partialled out. The previous prospect's expected value was a significant predictor of the current response for just 1 of the 14 participants, no more than would be expected by chance. For this participant, r2 = .04, and for all other participants r2 < .04. Similar analyses for the previous (a) response, (b) x, and (c) p also showed no sequential dependencies. (For this design, an r2  .08 can be detected with a power of 80%.) Across all participants, the mean slope of the best fitting regression lines did not differ significantly from zero for any predictor from the previous trial. Discussion In perceptual tasks where a series of stimuli are presented and a judgment is made after each stimulus, the response to the current stimulus is shown to depend on the stimuli (or responses; the two are normally highly correlated) on previous trials. In other words, the response on the current trial is systematically biased by (some aspect of) the previous trial. Some authors (e.g., Birnbaum, 1992) have suggested that judgments about risky prospects might be similarly affected. Here, CE judgments for simple prospects did not show sequential Prospect Relativity 28 dependencies like those shown in the analogous perceptual judgment tasks. There was little carryover of information from one trial to the next. This finding is consistent with Mellers et al.'s (1992) result, where the buying prices of a set of critical prospects were at most only slightly influenced by the expected value of (previously encountered) filler prospects. Experiment 4 Experiments 1 to 3 investigated the effect of context in CE judgment tasks. Careful discussion by Luce (2000) highlighted the difference between judged CEs, where participants provide a single judgment of the value of a prospect, and choice CEs, derived from a series of choices between risky prospects and fixed amounts. For example, for the kinds of prospects with large amounts and moderate probabilities used here, judged CEs are larger than choice CEs (see, e.g., Bostic, Herrnstein, & Luce, 1990). The preference reversal phenomenon (see, e.g., Lichtenstein & Slovic, 1971) is evidence that there is often a discrepancy between choicebased and CE-based methods of assessing utility (see also Tversky, Sattath, & Slovic, 1988). Indeed, Luce went as far as to advocate developing separate theories for judged and choice CEs. Experiment 4 investigated context effects in a choice-based procedure rather than a judged CE-based procedure. Participants made a single choice from a set of simple prospects of the form "p chance of x" where the probability of winning was traded off against the amount that could be won. The context was provided by manipulating the range of values of p (and therefore of x) offered. Method Participants. Ninety-one undergraduate and postgraduate students from the University of Warwick took part. Ages ranged from 18 to 40 years, with a mean age of 26 years. An approximately equal number of male and female participants took part. None had previously participated in any other experiment described in this article. Payment was determined by playing the prospect selected by each participant, and winnings were between £0 and £2. Prospect Relativity 29 Design. Participants were each offered a set of simple prospects of the form "p chance of x." Within the set, the probability of winning and the win amount were traded off against one another, and thus the choice was between a large probability of winning a small amount through to a smaller probability of winning a larger amount. Ten prospects were used: "50% chance of £50," "55% chance of £45," ..., "95% chance of £5." If utility is assumed to be a simple power function of x, as is standardly assumed in economics, with exponent that is u(x) = x the EU of each prospect can be calculated.7 Figure 10 plots utility as a function of the probability of winning p for different curvatures of the utility function (values of . For a risk-neutral person ( = 1.0), for whom utility is proportional to monetary value, the probability of winning for the prospect with the maximum utility is p = .5. For a risk-averse person ( < 1.0), the prospect with maximum utility has a larger probability of winning a smaller amount; the maximum falls at higher p for lower . The key observation is that the prospect with maximum utility in the set is determined by the level of risk aversion . Thus, a participant's choice of prospect can be mapped directly onto a degree of risk aversion. There were three between-participants conditions in the experiment. In the free-choice condition, all 10 prospects were presented. In two other conditions, the choice of prospects was limited to either the first or the second half of the prospects available in the free-choice condition. In the more risky condition, the prospects ranged from a "50% chance of £50" to a "70% chance of £30." In the less risky condition, the prospects ranged from a "75% chance of £25" to a "95% chance of £5." Procedure. Each participant was presented with a sheet listing a set of prospects. The prospects were presented in an ordered table, with a row for each prospect and columns headed "chance of winning" and "amount to win." Probabilities were presented as percentages. Participants were asked to choose one prospect from the set to play. Before making their choice, they were given an explanation of how the prospect would be played. The selected Prospect Relativity 30 prospect was played, and participants were paid according to its outcome, multiplied by an experiment exchange rate (0.002). Results The results are displayed in Table 1. Blank cells indicate that the prospect was not available for selection in that condition. Two hypotheses were tested. The first was that participants are sensitive to the absolute values of prospect attributes and are unaffected by the choice options. According to this hypothesis, in the restricted choice conditions, participants should have chosen the prospect in the set that was nearest to the prospect they would have chosen under free-choice conditions. For example, in the more risky condition, only 5 participants selected the prospect "70% chance of £30" (less risky prospects were not available), but in the free-choice condition, 3 + 6 + 3 + 1 + 5 + 1 = 19 participants selected the prospect "70% chance of £30" or one less risky. A 2 x 2 contingency table was constructed to test the hypothesis that there was no difference in the proportion of people selecting the prospect "70% chance of £30" or one less risky between the two conditions. The difference in proportions was significant, Fisher's exact p = .0002. An analogous table was constructed to test the difference between the less risky and free choice conditions. Again, the difference in proportions was significant, Fisher's exact p = .0029. In conclusion, we can reject the hypothesis that participants in the restricted-choice conditions chose the prospect in the set nearest to the prospect they would have chosen under free-choice conditions and were otherwise uninfluenced by the set of options. The second hypothesis tested was that, although there may be some effect of the choices available, there would still be some effect of the absolute magnitude of prospect attributes. If so, we would expect a tendency for participants in the most risky condition to choose the least risky prospect available and vice versa. However, if participants' choices were determined solely by the set of available prospects, then the distribution of responses across options (from the most risky to the least risky) should not differ across the more risky and less Prospect Relativity 31 risky conditions. There was no significant difference, 2(4, N = 61) = 2.89, p = .5767. In other words, there is no evidence that the absolute riskiness of a prospect had any influence on the choices made in each of the restricted-choice conditions. For this chi-squared test, a difference in J. Cohen's (1988) w = 0.45 which corresponds to a 2(4) = 27.45 can be detected with 80% power. Discussion Participants were asked to select a single prospect from a set to play. Within the set, the probability of winning a prospect was reduced as the amount that could be won was increased. Thus, each participant faced a choice between prospects offering small amounts with high probability through to larger amounts with a lower probability. In the restricted conditions, participants were offered only a subset of the prospects available. If participants' preferences were unaffected by the set of options provided, they should simply have chosen the prospect closest to the prospect they would select under free-choice conditions. However, the distribution of choices differed significantly from those expected under this prediction. Instead, the set of options available seemed to determine participants' preferences, and there was no significant evidence that participants were sensitive to the absolute level of risk implicit in a prospect. In conclusion, the level of risk aversion shown by a participant was shown here to be a function of the set of prospects offered. We know of only one other experiment where the effects of the context provided by the choice set has been shown to affect the prospect chosen. In an unpublished study by Payne, Bettman, and Simonson (reported in Simonson & Tversky, 1992), participants were asked to make a choice between a pair of three-outcome prospects. Adding a third prospect that was dominated by one of the original prospects but not the other significantly increased the proportion of times the (original) dominating prospect was selected over the (original) nondominating prospect. This effect has also been seen when making nonrisky decisions where, for example, participants chose between $6 or a famous brand pen. The introduction of Prospect Relativity 32 a pen from a lesser known brandname increased the proportion of participants selecting the famous brand pen and reduced the proportion selecting the $6 (see Simonson & Tversky, 1992, for this and other examples). The notion of trade-off contrast, where participants who are assumed to have little knowledge about the trade-off between two properties, deduce what the average trade-off is from the current or earlier choice sets, can account for this type of data. However, it is not immediately obvious how the notion of trade-off contrast might account for the results of Experiment 4. Across both contexts, the trade-off between probability and amount was constant (as the chance of winning the prospect was increased by 5%, the amount to win fell by £5). Instead, it seems that participants had no absolute grip of the level of risk implicit in each prospect in the choice set and instead chose a prospect with reference to its riskiness relative to the other prospects in the set. This demonstration of prospect relativity in choice is consistent with that described in earlier experiments, where CE judgments were used. Experiment 5 Our final experiment was designed to investigate the extent to which a choice between two prospects is affected by preceding context. Thus, this experiment mirrors Experiment 3, but with actual choices rather than CE judgments. On each trial, participants chose between a sure amount of money and a prospect offering a larger amount with a known probability. Let us informally call a trial risky (or safe) to the degree that participants are expected to prefer the risky prospect (or the sure amount of money). For example, we expected people to prefer the risky prospect over the sure amount more often in (a) a "50% chance of £100" or £10 for sure compared with (b) a "50% chance of £100" or £40 for sure. Half of the trials, the common trials, were given to all participants and were designed so that the sure amount was such that a typical, moderately risk-averse participant would be indifferent between the sure amount and the risky prospect. The other half of the trials were filler trials, and their properties Prospect Relativity 33 were manipulated between participants. For half of the participants, the filler trials were constructed so that only a very risk-averse individual would be indifferent to the sure amount and the risky prospect. For these risky trials, most participants should have favored the risky prospect. For the other half of the participants, the filler trials were constructed so that only relatively risk-neutral participants would favor the risky prospect. For these safe trials, most participants should have favored the sure amount. The intention was to assess whether the riskiness of the filler trials would affect choices on the common trials. If participants represented current prospects relative to previous prospects, then the common trials should have seemed relatively safe if the filler trials were risky, and participants should have favored the safe, sure amount. Conversely, if the filler trials were safe, then the common trials should have seemed relatively risky, and participants should have favored the risky prospect. Method Participants. Thirty-five undergraduate and postgraduate students from the University of Warwick took part in the experiment and were paid £5 for participating in this and three other related experiments. Ages ranged from 18 to 30 years, with a mean of 22 years. Two thirds of participants were female. Design. Thirty-six trials were generated, each of which comprised a simple prospect of the form "p chance of x" and an amount offered for certain. The amounts £100, £200, £300, £400, £500, and £600 were crossed with the win probabilities of .1, .2, .4, .6, .8, and .9 to give 36 prospects. Half of the trials were selected at random and consistently used to set the context. For half of the participants, the fixed amount offered on these trials was low, and for the other half of the participants, the fixed amount was high. The other half of the trials was common to both groups, and the fixed amounts were at an intermediate level. A sure amount was generated by using Equation 2.

برای دانلود متن کامل این مقاله و بیش از 32 میلیون مقاله دیگر ابتدا ثبت نام کنید

ثبت نام

اگر عضو سایت هستید لطفا وارد حساب کاربری خود شوید

منابع مشابه

Prospect relativity: how choice options influence decision under risk.

In many theories of decision under risk (e.g., expected utility theory, rank-dependent utility theory, and prospect theory), the utility of a prospect is independent of other options in the choice set. The experiments presented here show a large effect of the available options, suggesting instead that prospects are valued relative to one another. The judged certainty equivalent for a prospect i...

متن کامل

Prospect Relativity 1 Running Head: PROSPECT RELATIVITY Prospect Relativity: How Choice Options Influence Decision Under Risk

In many theories of decision under risk (e.g., expected utility theory, rank dependent utility theory, and prospect theory) the utility or value of a prospect is independent of other prospects or options in the choice set. The experiments presented here show a large effect of the available options set, suggesting instead that prospects are valued relative to one another. The judged certainty eq...

متن کامل

Financial Prospect Relativity: Context Effects in Financial Decision-Making Under Risky

We report three studies in which methodologies from psychophysics are adapted to investigate context effects on individual financial decision-making under risk. The aim was to determine how the range and the rank of the options offered as saving amounts and levels of investment risk influence people’s decisions about these variables. In the range manipulation, participants were presented with e...

متن کامل

Framing effects and risk-sensitive decision making.

Prospect theory suggests that people are risk-averse when facing gains, but risk-prone when facing losses, a pattern known as the framing effect. Although framing effects have been widely demonstrated, few studies have investigated framing effects under conditions of need. Risk-sensitivity theory predicts that decision makers should prefer high-risk options in situations of high need, when lowe...

متن کامل

Jack S. Levy Applications of Prospect Theory to Political Science

Prospect theory is an alternative theory of choice under conditions of risk, and deviates from expected utility theory by positing that people evaluate choices with respect to gains and losses from a reference point. They tend to overweight losses with respect to comparable gains and engage in risk-averse behavior with respect to gains and risk-acceptant behavior with respect to losses. They al...

متن کامل

ذخیره در منابع من


  با ذخیره ی این منبع در منابع من، دسترسی به آن را برای استفاده های بعدی آسان تر کنید

برای دانلود متن کامل این مقاله و بیش از 32 میلیون مقاله دیگر ابتدا ثبت نام کنید

ثبت نام

اگر عضو سایت هستید لطفا وارد حساب کاربری خود شوید

عنوان ژورنال:

دوره   شماره 

صفحات  -

تاریخ انتشار 2009